Wikiprojekt:SKFiz/brudnopis/no-cloning theorem

Szablon:Quantum Twierdzenie o zakazie klonowania, wynikające z mechaniki kwantowej, jest zasadą, zabraniającą stworzenia identycznych kopii dowolnego nieznanego stanu kantowego. Zostało udowodnione przez Williama Wootersa i Wojciecha Żurka oraz niezależnie Dennisa Dieksa w roku 1982 i znalazło zastosowanie w komputerach kwantowych i innych dziedzinach.

Stany układów można że sobą splątać. Na przykład, można użyć bramki CNOT i bramki Hadamarda do splątania dwóch kubitów, lecz nie jest to klonowaniem. Żaden stan określony nie może zostać przypisany do podsystemu stanu splątanego. Klonowanie jest procesem, którego wynikiem są stany niesplątane z identycznymi wynikami pomiarów.

Według izraelskiego fizyka Ashera Peresa, publikacja twierdzenia o zakazie klonowania opierała się na pomyśle Nicka Herberta na nadświetlne urządzenie komunikacyjne wykorzystujące splątanie kwantowe.

Suppose the state of a quantum system A, which we wish to copy, is   (see bra-ket notation). In order to make a copy, we take a system B with the same state space and initial state  . The initial, or blank, state must be independent of  , of which we have no prior knowledge. The composite system is then described by the tensor product, and its state is

 

There are only two ways to manipulate the composite system. We could perform an observation, which irreversibly collapses the system into some eigenstate of the observable, corrupting the information contained in the qubit. This is obviously not what we want. Alternatively, we could control the Hamiltonian of the system, and thus the time evolution operator U (for a time independent Hamiltonian,  , where   is called the generator of translations in time) up to some fixed time interval, which yields a unitary operator. Then U acts as a copier provided that

 

for all possible states   in the state space (including  ). Since U is unitary, it preserves the inner product:

 

and since quantum mechanical states are assumed to be normalized, it follows that

 

This implies that either   (in which case  ) or   is orthogonal to   (in which case  ). However, this is not the case for two arbitrary states. While orthogonal states in a specifically chosen basis  , for example:

 

and

 

fit the requirement that  , this result does not hold for more general quantum states. Apparently U cannot clone a general quantum state. This proves the no-cloning theorem.

Generalizations edytuj

Mixed states and nonunitary operations edytuj

In the statement of the theorem, two assumptions were made: the state to be copied is a pure state and the proposed copier acts via unitary time evolution. These assumptions cause no loss of generality. If the state to be copied is a mixed state, it can be purified. Similarly, an arbitrary quantum operation can be implemented via introducing an ancilla and performing a suitable unitary evolution. Thus the no-cloning theorem holds in full generality.

Arbitrary sets of states edytuj

Non-clonability can be seen as a property of arbitrary sets of quantum states. If we know that a system's state is one of the states in some set S, but we do not know which one, can we prepare another system in the same state? If the elements of S are pairwise orthogonal, the answer is always yes: for any such set there exists a measurement which will ascertain the exact state of the system without disturbing it, and once we know the state we can prepare another system in the same state. If S contains two elements that are not pairwise orthogonal (in particular, the set of all quantum states includes such pairs) then an argument like that given above shows that the answer is no.

The cardinality of an unclonable set of states may be as small as two, so even if we can narrow down the state of a quantum system to just two possibilities, we still cannot clone it in general (unless the states happen to be orthogonal).

Another way of stating the no-cloning theorem is that amplification of a quantum signal can only happen with respect to some orthogonal basis. This is related to the emergence of classical probability rules in quantum decoherence.

No-cloning in a classical context edytuj

There is a classical analogue to the quantum no-cloning theorem, which we might state as follows: given only the result of one flip of a (possibly biased) coin, we cannot simulate a second, independent toss of the same coin. The proof of this statement uses the linearity of classical probability, and has exactly the same structure as the proof of the quantum no-cloning theorem. Thus if we wish to claim that no-cloning is a uniquely quantum result, some care is necessary in stating the theorem. One way of restricting the result to quantum mechanics is to restrict the states to pure states, where a pure state is defined to be one that is not a convex combination of other states. The classical pure states are pairwise orthogonal, but quantum pure states are not.

Wnioski edytuj

Zasada nie klonowania zabrania używania klasycznych kodów korekcyjnych do stanów kwantowych. Przykładowo, nie można zrobić kopii zapasowej stanu w komputerze kwantowym aby zapobiec kolejnym błędom. Korekcja błędów jest kluczowa dla obliczeń kwantowych, i przez pewien czas uważano to za ograniczenie na komputer kwantowy. W 1995 Peter Shor oraz Andrew Steane odświeżyli koncepcję obliczeń kwantowych w oparciu o kwantowe kody korekcyjne, które obchodzą ograniczenia zasady nie klonowania.

Podobnie, klonowanie może naruszyć zakaz klasycznej teleportacji.

  • The no-cloning theorem does not prevent superluminal communication via quantum entanglement, as cloning is a sufficient condition for such communication, but not a necessary one. Nevertheless, consider the EPR thought experiment, and suppose quantum states could be cloned. Assume parts of a maximally entangled Bell state are distributed to Alice and Bob. Alice could send bits to Bob in the following way: If Alice wishes to transmit a "0", she measures the spin of her electron in the z direction, collapsing Bob's state to either   or  . To transmit "1", Alice does nothing to her qubit. Bob creates many copies of his electron's state, and measures the spin of each copy in the z direction. Bob will know that Alice has transmitted a "0" if all his measurements will produce the same result; otherwise, his measurements will have outcomes +1/2 and −1/2 with equal probability. This would allow Alice and Bob to communicate across space-like separations.

Niedoskonałe klonowanie edytuj

Mimo że jest niemożliwe zrobienie idealnych kopii nieznanego stanu kwantowego, można wytworzyć niedoskonałe kopie. Proces ten może być przeprowadzony poprzez użycie większego systemu pomocniczego który będzie klonowany i zastosować przekształcenie unitarne do całego systemu. Jeżeli przekształcenie jest wybrane poprawne niektóre elementy układu mogą ewoluować w przybliżone kopie wyjściowego systemu. Klonowanie kwantowe może zostać użyte do ataków podsłuchujących na protokoły kryptograficzne.

See also edytuj

References edytuj


Other sources edytuj

  • V. Buzek and M. Hillery, Quantum cloning, Physics World 14 (11) (2001), pp. 25–29.

Category:Quantum information science Category:Physics theorems Category:Articles containing proofs

de:No-Cloning-Theorem fr:Impossibilité du clonage quantique it:Teorema di no-cloning quantistico ru:Теорема о запрете клонирования zh:不可克隆原理